©
2005 Philosophy Now. All rights
reserved.
Scott
O’Reilly reviews Peter Singer‘s review of George W. Bush‘s statements on
ethics.
Inquiring
after the ethics of George W. Bush might seem to many like a Herculean task,
and possibly doomed to failure, but worth a try anyway. Peter Singer, one of
the world's best-known philosophers, has taken up this daunting challenge in
his The President of Good and Evil: The Ethics of George W. Bush, and the
result is a superbly instructive lesson on the strengths and limits of applying
the methods of philosophy to current events.
Immanuel
Kant once wrote that “out of the crooked timber of humanity, no straight thing
was ever made.” The thought is worth bearing in mind as Singer attempts to
apply the sharp edge of logic and sound reasoning against the sometimes-twisted
reasoning proffered by Bush and his administration. As Plato recognized long
ago, philosophers are rarely kings, and kings are rarely philosophers, hence it
might be unreasonable from the outset to expect Bush's public utterances and
policies to conform to any rational understanding or explanation. Perhaps Bush
is simply a political animal, telling voters whatever they want to hear so long
as it furthers his acquisition of power. In Bush's case we might call this the
‘Machiavelli from Mayberry' conjecture – a working assumption that Bush is a
cynical operator with the cunning of a fox, and the strength and ferocity of a
lion, but who attempts to pass himself off as a meek and humble lamb. Singer
rejects this assumption, deciding to take Bush's pronouncements at face value,
in effect asking if Bush's words and deeds stand up to philosophical scrutiny.
In this, Singer is very much performing the role of a modern day Socrates,
asking common sense questions, applying clear reasoning, and using his
interlocutors own words as the standard by which they are judged. And like
Socrates, Singer makes for a rather formidable gadfly.
Singer
examines the president's public statements and positions on all the key issues
– tax cuts, environmental policy, stem cell research, and the wars in
Afghanistan and Iraq – and he repeatedly uncovers glaring contradictions that
would appear to undermine not only Bush's credibility, but also the coherence
of Bush's stated policy objectives. For instance, he zeroes in on the
administration's extraordinarily inconsistent – if not duplicitous – conduct
surrounding the march to war against Iraq. As Singer notes, early in the Bush
administration key figure such as Colin Powell and Condoleezza Rice went on
record saying that Saddam had been disarmed and contained. Within months the
administration had flip-flopped, with all the key figures pushing the position
that Saddam had stockpiles of WMD that posed an immanent threat requiring a
pre-emptive invasion. Singer demonstrates how the Bush administration
prematurely pulled out U.N. weapons inspectors from Iraq and then failed to
secure a second U.N. Security Council resolution that would explicitly
authorize force. Failing to see the U.N. weapons inspection process through
meant that the subsequent U.S. invasion of Iraq failed to meet the criteria for
a Just War (according to which the use of force is only a last resort when all
other means have failed). But it was also, as Singer points out, a violation of
international law, the U.N. Charter, and the U.S. Constitution all at the same
time. Ironically, Bush argued that in failing to provide a second resolution
authorizing force the U.N was making itself irrelevant, blithely ignoring the
fact that it was the Bush administration's unilateral actions that were
undermining the U.N.
In
the end, the U.S. would fail to find Saddam's alleged WMD, but when confronted
with this fact Bush reacted by accusing his critics of ‘historical
revisionism.'
The
shifting rationales, contradictory pronouncements, and legal doubletalk
convinced many observers that they had entered some Orwellian alternative
universe where a ubiquitous Catch-22 clause is forever trumping the laws of
logic and sound reasoning. If no engineer or architect could expect to ignore
the principles of geometry and have their work hold up in the real world, how
could the Bush administration so consistently disregard the standards of
cogency in the pursuit of statecraft? Perhaps the answer is that they couldn't,
and that the troubled occupation of Iraq serves as something of a reductio ad
absurdumon the Bush administration's ‘faith-based' foreign policy.
Singer
takes the Bush administration to task for allowing ideology to trump empiricism
and sound reasoning. In a particularly effective passage Singer cites a story
by the 19th century English mathematician and philosopher William Clifford,
which illustrates the perils of basing ones ethics or actions on belief.
Clifford asks us to imagine a shipowner who knows his ship could do with a
costly inspection and repairs, but sincerely believes that Providence will see
the ship and its passengers through on a difficult voyage. Clifford argues that
the shipowner's belief was not acquired “by honestly earning it in patient
investigation, but by stifling his doubts.” When the ship sinks its owner's
guilt is not absolved by the sincerity of his faith; indeed he is culpable
precisely for substituting belief in place of practical measures.
Singer's
point is hard to miss. Even if Bush was entirely sincere in his belief that
Saddam possessed WMD, that in no way excuses a general pattern whereby the Bush
administration ignored evidence that might contradict its preconceptions.
Singer isn't the only philosopher who finds an ideological style of leadership
troubling. Karl Popper argued that political and social progress arises not
from adhering to timeless principals, unchallenged assumptions, or sacred
scriptures, but from trial and error. This is a tremendously simple but
powerful idea. It suggests that political truth isn't something a farsighted,
ethically-infallible leader intuits from on high, but rather the hard won
achievement of putting ideas and institutions to the test and seeing which ones
hold up and serve the common good. Time and again, Singer argues, Bush eschews
this trial and error approach, particularly in the case of stem cell research,
and by ignoring scientific evidence in the case of Global Warming.
Singer
examines Bush's ethics from a number of points of view – Utilitarianism, a
Judeo-Christian value system, and a Libertarian perspective – and in every case
fails to find a consistent framework that would make sense of Bush's moral
reasoning. Turning to psychology Singer speculates that Bush's sometimes-rigid
adherence to the ‘letter of the law' (but not its spirit) indicates that the
president is stuck at what Harvard psychologist Lawrence Kohlberg termed the
Conventional Stage of morality, which he describes as, “an orientation toward
authority, fixed rules, and the maintenance of social order.” Kohlberg
describes this as the level of moral development most often associated with 13
year olds. (The idea that the president of the United States has not yet
graduated to the Post-conventional level of moral reasoning associated with
Kantian-style universal principals is a troubling conjecture, but it might
explain a lot).
The
conclusion Singer finds most plausible regarding George W. Bush's ethics may be
the most disturbing. Singer notes that a high number of key Bush administration
officials are disciples of a philosopher called Leo Strauss. Strauss, who
taught at the University of Chicago until his death in 1973, argued that many
of the great ancient philosophers, particularly the Greeks, wrote in a kind of
code. Only a select intellectual elite were capable of absorbing the esoteric
meaning latent in the texts, while the hoi polloi took everything at face
value. The Straussians believe that the masses are simply not equipped to
handle the often-grim truths that underlie political and world affairs
(remember the old saying: there are two things you never want to see being
made, sausages and legislation). But according to Singer the Straussians go
even further, suggesting that sometimes the ‘aristocratic gentlemen' charged
with governing a polity lack the sophistication to handle the truth. In such
cases the elite advisors must be prepared to mislead not just the masses with
noble lies, but also the leader. Singer points out that this might explain why
Bush's false assertion that Iraq was trying to acquire uranium from Niger
stayed in his State of the Union address while other agencies like the CIA and
the State Department regarded it as untrue. It might also explain why Bush
appeared on Polish television telling viewers that the U.S. had discovered
mobile weapons labs in Iraq, a story disproven weeks before. However, the idea
that Bush could claim in the presence of U.N. Secretary General Kofi Annan that
“we gave him [Saddam] a chance to allow the inspectors in, and he wouldn't let
them in,” strikes Singer as almost too bizarre for belief – Bush had, after
all, recalled the inspectors himself before their job was completed. Singer
goes so far as to speculate that Bush was intoxicated, on drugs, or perhaps out
of his mind when he uttered such obviously preposterous statements. But Singer
quickly discounts such explanations, finding it far more plausible that the
president may in fact be a patsy or a puppet – with the Machiavellians pulling
the strings on the man from Mayberry.
Emerson
once wrote, “A foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds.” Great
statesmen often exhibit tremendous contradiction in their personalities and
their policies. But what happens when a given leader repeatedly utters
statements that contradict their previous statement, as well as reality? A
disciple of Machiavelli might argue that this is what leaders are often called
to do for the public good. For instance, most of us would probably agree with
Winston Churchill that, “occasionally the truth needs a bodyguard of lies.”
Singer, however, makes a persuasive case that with George W. Bush those
supposedly guarding the truth have mugged it instead. If so, it is worth
remembering another thought from Churchill: “A democratic people can face any
adversity with fortitude, provided they believe their leaders are leveling with
them, and not living in a fool's paradise.”
©
Scott O'Reilly 2005
Scott
O'Reilly is a contributor to The Great Thinkers A-Z (2004) and writes a monthly
column of political humor for Compass Magazine .
•
The President of Good and Evil: The Ethics of George W. Bushby Peter Singer,
2004 (Dutton, $25/Granta £8.99 paperback) 1-86207-693-6. This book is at the
Philosophy Now Bookstore.